Notes on set theory

Much of this (up to and including cofinality) is taken from Set Theory by Thomas Jech [Jec03], but you can probably find it in any reasonable set theory book. The rest is from Hovey's book Model Categories [Hov99].

Well-ordered sets

A linearly ordered set (P, < ) is well-ordered if every nonempty subset of P has a least element. A map f of ordered sets is increasing if xyf (x) ≥ f (y).

Lemma 1.1   Suppose that (W, < ) is well-ordered. If f : WW is an increasing function, then f (x) ≥ x for all xW.

Corollary 1.2   The only automorphism of a well-ordered set is the identity.

Corollary 1.3   If W1 and W2 are isomorphic well-ordered sets, there is a unique isomorphism between them.

Given a well-ordered set W and an element uW, the initial segment given by u is {xW : x < u}.

Lemma 1.4   No well-ordered set is isomorphic to an initial segment of itself.

Theorem 1.5   For any well-ordered sets W1 and W2, exactly one of the following holds:
  1. W1 is isomorphic to W2.
  2. W1 is isomorphic to an initial segment of W2.
  3. W2 is isomorphic to an initial segment of W1.

If W1 and W2 are isomorphic well-ordered sets, say that they have the same order type.

Ordinals

A set T is transitive if every element of T is a subset of T. (That is, T is a subset of its power set.) A set is an ordinal number (or an ordinal) if it is transitive and well-ordered by ∈. For ordinals α and β, define α < β if α ∈ β.

The class of ordinals, Ord, has these properties:

So define α + 1 to be α ∪ {α}; this is called the successor to α. If α = β + 1 for some β, then α is called a successor ordinal. If α is not a successor ordinal, then α = sup{β : β < α}, and α is called a limit ordinal.

Theorem 2.1   Every well-ordered set is isomorphic to a unique ordinal number.

Let β be a limit ordinal. A β-sequence is a function whose domain is β:

aξ : ξ < β⟩.

If ⟨ αξ : ξ < β⟩ is a nondecreasing sequence of ordinals (so ξ < η implies αξ < αη), then the limit of the sequence is

limξ → β αξ = sup {αξ : ξ < β}.

Examples of ordinals:

0 = {}    
1 = {0}    
2 = {0, 1}    
3 = {0, 1, 2}    
...    
ω = {0, 1, 2, ... }    
ω + 1 = {0, 1, 2, ... ;ω}    
...    

Cardinals

An ordinal α is a cardinal number if |α| ≠ |β| for all β < α.

If W is well-ordered, there is an ordinal α such that |W| = |α|, so let |W| denote the least ordinal α such that |W| = |α|. (By the axiom of choice, every set can be well-ordered, so we can extend this notation to any set W.)

Note: all infinite cardinals are limit ordinals.

Cofinality and κ-filtered ordinals

Let α > 0 be a limit ordinal. An increasing β-sequence ⟨ αξ : ξ < β⟩, for β a limit ordinal, is cofinal in α if limξ → β αξ = α. Similarly, A ⊂ α is cofinal in α if sup A = α.

For α an infinite limit ordinal, let cf α be the least limit ordinal β such that there is an increasing β-sequence ⟨ αξ : ξ < β⟩ with limξ → β αξ = α; this is called the cofinality of α. Note that cf α ≤ α always.

From [Hov99, Section 2.1]: given a cardinal κ, an ordinal α is κ-filtered if it is a limit ordinal and, if A ⊆α and |A| ≤ κ, then sup A < α. This holds if and only if the cofinality of α is greater than κ.

For example, if κ is finite, then a κ-filtered ordinal is just an infinite limit ordinal. If κ is infinite, the smallest κ-filtered ordinal is the first cardinal κ1 larger than κ.

Smallness

(This material is taken from [Hov99, Section 2.1].)

Suppose that C is a category with all small colimits, D is a collection of morphisms of C, A is an object of C and κ is a cardinal. We say that A is κ-small relative to D if, for all κ-filtered ordinals λ and all λ-sequences

X0X1 → ... → Xβ → ...

such that each map XβXβ+1 is in D, the map of sets

colimβ < λ C(A, Xβ) → C(A, colimβ < λ Xβ)

is an isomorphism. We say that A is small relative to D if it is κ-small for some κ. We say that A is small if it is small relative to the whole category C. We say that A is finite relative to D if it is κ-small relative to D for some finite cardinal κ, and similarly, A is finite if it is finite relative to C. Finite means that maps from A commute with colimits of arbitrary λ-sequences, for any limit ordinal λ.

Examples:

Bibliography

Hov99
M. Hovey, Model categories, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1999.

Jec03
Thomas Jech, Set theory, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003, The third millennium edition, revised and expanded.

About this document ...

Notes on set theory

This document was generated using the LaTeX2HTML translator Version 2002 (1.62) (and then heavily edited by John Palmieri).

Copyright © 1993, 1994, 1995, 1996, Nikos Drakos, Computer Based Learning Unit, University of Leeds.
Copyright © 1997, 1998, 1999, Ross Moore, Mathematics Department, Macquarie University, Sydney.

The command line arguments were:
latex2html -no_math -html_version 3.2,math -split 0 set-theory.tex

The translation was initiated by John Palmieri on 2004-04-21


John Palmieri 2004-04-21